Deconstruction
Author: James E. Faulconer
Deconstruction
James E. Faulconer (Revised 15 June 1998)
Some words are their own worst enemies. Deconstruction is one of them. Like existentialism,
special, liberal, conservative, and postmodern, its meaning is often so vague as to be useless.
Coined, more or less, by the contemporary French philosopher, Jacques Derrida, the word
deconstruction began its life in the late sixties, but it has only become part of the American
vocabulary in the last ten years or so. In that time, however, it has moved from a technical
philosophical term adopted by literary critics for their related uses to a word that pops up in
offhand remarks by everyone from botanists to the clergy. Whatever its original meaning, in its
now widespread use, deconstruction has come to mean "tear down" or "destroy" (usually when
the object is nonmaterial).
These uses of the word have been anything but charitable. To the irritation of older professors as
well as Derrida (whom older professors often think of as "the enemy"), many in literature have
used the word, positively and negatively, to mean something like, "playing with texts to show that
they have no meaning." In the Anglo-American academy and to a lesser extent also in Continental
Europe, the result has been that those who talk about deconstruction positively often do so in
simplistic ways and those who criticize it take the simpletons as representative of deconstruction.
One side creates the straw men, the other side burns them down, but neither actually gets to the
point of discussing deconstruction. Neither has the everyday use of the word as a synonym for
destruction helped it avoid a bad reputation. Today, at best, to deconstruct something is to tear it
apart. At worst, it is to be disrespectful and nihilistic.
In the face of these assaults on the word deconstruction, I'm sure it is too late to save it from the
fate of meaninglessness or synonymy with destruction. On the other hand, it may not be too late
to say something about how the word began its life and what the philosophy called deconstruction
is about. That may not save the word, but that shouldn't surprise us. The devil usually gets all the
good words. That may not surprise us, but perhaps knowing something about the word and how
Derrida originally meant it to work may help us understand what it means as a philosophical term
and what the movement called deconstruction is about.
Derrida takes the word deconstruction from the work of Martin Heidegger. In the summer of
1927, Martin Heidegger delivered a lecture course now published under the title, Basic Problems
of Phenomenology. Given the topic of his lectures, Heidegger appropriately begins them with a
discussion of the nature of philosophy and, particularly of the philosophical movement called
phenomenology. Borrowing creatively from his teacher, Edmund Husserl, Heidegger says that
phenomenology is the name for a method of doing philosophy; he says that the method includes
three steps -- reduction, construction, and destruction -- and he explains that these three are
mutually pertinent to one another. Construction necessarily involves destruction, he says, and then
he identifies destruction with deconstruction, Abbau (20-23). Heidegger explains what he means
by philosophical destruction by using an ordinary German word that we can translate literally
"unbuild."
The lexical and historical connection of deconstruction to destruction is obvious, but Heidegger
does not mean by Abbau quite what we mean by either destruction or disassembly. He uses
Abbau to show that in his method the word destruction does not mean what we might often mean
by it. He explains what he means by Abbau -- deconstruction -- to clarify further that he does
not simply mean "taking things apart." As Heidegger conceived deconstruction, it was an answer
to a philosophical problem: "All philosophical discussion, even the most radical attempt to begin
all over again, is pervaded by traditional concepts and thus by traditional horizons and traditional
angles of approach" (Basic Problems 22). Unfortunately, however, we cannot assume that these
concepts, horizons, and approaches are the best ones for dealing with the things they supposedly
explain. There is a world "out there."(1) Our problem is that our only rational access to that world
is linguistic, which might make us mistakenly to believe that our understanding of the world is
always derivative from our language. If we add our suspicion to Heidegger's point that we have
inherited our concepts and words from others who themselves had to work with inherited
concepts and words and we quickly come to a question: How, then, can we think about the world
productively? How can we avoid reducing understanding to something relative only to a particular
language and history?
Like every other philosopher in the nineteenth- and twentieth-centuries, Heidegger does not
believe there is an autonomous tool called reason that we use irrespective of our language, time,
circumstances, or interests, to criticize ideas. Thus, since we seem unable to begin from such a
rational zero point, free of any already given concepts, terms, or approaches, it appears that we
are forced to repeat the past and its mistakes. If we must use concepts we've inherited from
others to do philosophy (or anything else), how can we ever get to anything new? How can we
get beyond whatever philosophical mistakes our intellectual forebears may have made? Aren't we
condemned to historicism and cultural relativism?(2)
Ironically, given much of the current discussion of Heidegger's work and the work that derives
from his, Heidegger's answer is, "No." We can use these concepts, horizons, and approaches
against themselves to discover what produced them. We might, for example, think about
Aristotle's discussion of form and matter, using those very terms to show their inadequacy. What,
after all, is matter? Any answer I give is in terms of another form rather than in terms of matter.
Questions: "What is that desk made of; what is its material?" Answer: "Wood." But the word
wood gives us a form, not a matter. I can ask, "What is the wood made of?" and give a reasonable
answer, though one still in terms of form. As we use the terms matter and form against
themselves, what starts out looking like a perfectly sensible question becomes problematic. By
problematizing the distinction, we begin to get at least a glimpse of the problem to which Aristotle
was responding. Perhaps we begin to wonder -- to think -- in the same way that he did. If we
do, perhaps we begin to do philosophy with regards to Aristotle's questions rather than simply to
repeat the scholarly exegesis of Aristotle's philosophy.
Derrida would say of this example that we can deconstruct the idea of form and matter. But what
he means by deconstruction differs from what Heidegger means. For one thing, rather than a
method or part of a method, for Derrida deconstruction is an attitude, in the root sense of that
word. It is a position one has with regard to something.
To think about the difference between Heidegger's and Derrida's notions of deconstruction,
consider an example: I am writing a book on community. I will work over it repeatedly until I am
satisfied that I am done. But what does done mean? Doesn't it mean "say everything I want to
say"? And what do I want it to say? Everything. Everything, that is, about what it means to be a
community. Of course, there will be this or that minor point that I may ignore or safely overlook,
but as long as something significant remains to be said about my topic or as long as the
connections of important points have not been made clear, I am not done. When I am done,
therefore, I have produced something that claims to say everything of importance on my topic;
that I have written the book on my topic is implicit in its existence as a book, even if I insert
footnotes and apologies and disclaimers to the contrary.
However, when I have finished the book and have (I hope) a publisher, what is the first thing I
will do? I'll write an introduction. But introductions are odd things. If they can say what the book
says, then what need is there for the book? If they can't, then what need is there for the
introduction? Sometimes they are appetizers, things designed to get people to read the book (or at
least to buy it). Most of the time, however, an introduction is a short version of the book, an
overview. It sets the problem in context, it shows the readers how important the problem or
solution is, it gives the argument in a more easily understood form. Introductions add to the book
to improve it, to supplement its work.
Thus, though the book implicitly claims to say everything needed, as a supplement, the
introduction says "one more thing" or "the same thing briefly," deconstructing the book's claim
to completeness and self-sufficiency. In deconstructing the book, the introduction doesn't show
us the irrelevance of the book. It doesn't show us that the book is meaningless. It doesn't show us
that just any interpretation of the book will do. It shows us that the book claims more than it can
deliver, that it has left something out though it claims to be complete. I take that to be the general
meaning of the word deconstruction as Derrida has used it: not just using our words and concepts
against themselves, but showing what has been left out or overlooked. In fact, better: showing
that something has been left out or overlooked, that omission is structural to any text -- and that
we can find those omissions in the structure of the text -- without necessarily being able to
specify what has been omitted.
Notice, however, that once, by means of a deconstruction, we have seen something that was
omitted, we won't be able to go back, insert the missing piece, and then be finally done. The
omission is structural to writing and explaining because it is structural to existence and
experience. Omission is unavoidable. The reason why is not difficult to see. For one thing, no one
can say everything about anything; things are never that simple, not simple things, especially not
"first things."
This inability to say everything is not a failure of language, something to be overcome. Neither is
it a point of new-age silliness or old-age magic (though it may be an origin of the latter). It is one
of the properties of things.(3) If I hold an object up before someone and ask her to tell me what she
sees, she can give a list of the thing's properties. If she works at it, she can make that list very
long. It may become ever more difficult to add things to the list, but there is really no end to what
she could truthfully say about the object. She can, for example, always relate it to another thing in
the universe or even to the list she is making. Though we seldom have any reason to go on and on
in such a way, there is, in principle, no end to the length of the description one can give of an
ordinary object. As a result, it is impossible to say everything about an object, material or
otherwise.
More important, the object itself shows that there is still more to be said. Every object shows
itself as a set of possibilities, not merely as a determinate thing. To see a particular object is to see
it in terms of possibilities. It is for example, to see the possibility of seeing the object from another
perspective without knowing what perspective that might be or what I might see from that other
perspective. To see one side of a chalk board eraser is to know (though usually only implicitly)
that there is another side. That there is more to see and, therefore, to say is not just an inference I
make when I see this side; the other side is not something I deduce from seeing this side. The fact
that there is more than what I see immediately is part and parcel of seeing an object at all, for I
don't see planes and surfaces and then deduce that they are objects. I see objects from the
beginning and, as objects, objects have aspects that don't meet the eye, aspects like their other
sides and things that I will only discover determinately on investigation. There is always more in
what I see than I can name. Kant might have called this fact about the excessive character of
perception one of the conditions for the possibility of having an experience at all. To perceive an
object is to know immediately that there is always more to be said. All experience is experience of
more, of possibility.
Most of the time these facts about describing things are quite irrelevant. For practical purposes I
need only say what needs to be said, not everything. (For an interesting discussion of this, though
not a deconstructive one, see Jerry Fodor's The Elm and the Expert.) I write a book for a purpose
and an audience. It is difficult, if not impossible to do otherwise. Even if doing otherwise is
possible, it isn't often a very good idea. Given that I would like to influence the ways we think
about community, there is nothing wrong with my writing for my purpose and audience. I should
do so.
After I write my book for a particular purpose and a particular audience, someone else can give a
straightforward interpretation of it with that purpose and audience in mind. If I have done my job
well, there will be general agreement about what I have said to that audience for that purpose.
However, once I have published the book, it is no longer simply mine. It may be taken up by other
audiences or used for other purposes. Or someone can ask about the effects of my having written
for my purpose and audience: did doing so leave someone out? someone who, perhaps, should
not have been left out? In addressing my purposes and audience, does the book fail to address a
topic that I could have or should have addressed? Does the text do something that I, perhaps,
never intended it to do? Are there political or ethical implications of what I have written that I
could not see but that should, nevertheless, be considered? Is something or someone excluded by
the very structure of the enterprise, whether the enterprise is that of writing my book or of
philosophy?
One way to address these kinds of questions would be to write a book or article about my book,
to criticize it for not doing what it should. Christian, Marxist, feminist, and moral criticism often
take this form. Another way would be to write another book on community that explicitly or
implicitly corrects the mistakes my book makes. My book will be, in fact, such a book. I write it
with certain previous books and ideas in mind, books and ideas that I think have made mistakes.
But these are not the only ways of responding to my book. Another is deconstruction (and
deconstruction can serve the ends of any of the other kinds of criticism, Christian, Marxist,
feminist, moral, etc.).
Deconstruction differs from other ways of addressing questions about a work in that, rather than
comparing the work to an external standard for what should be done (such as moral standards,
scientific standards, or political ideology), it looks for ways in which the book itself shows what it
has overlooked. Deconstruction is a form of what is called imminent critique. Derrida, for
example, writes about a footnote in Heidegger's Being and Time to show that -- as a careful
reading of the footnote will purportedly show -- the book's claims are problematic.(4) In fact,
Derrida argues that Heidegger's work undercuts itself.
Derrida's deconstruction, however, is different from ideological or moral criticism. Derrida does
not deconstruct Heidegger's work to show that Heidegger should have written the book better.
Unlike a good book reviewer, Derrida is not repairing Heidegger's work for him, presuming that
with these corrections we will have, at least in principle, a better work. Deconstructive criticism is
not intended to suggest a way to make the book finally complete, but to show its necessary
incompleteness. Deconstruction is used to show that a work does not adequately address
something, not that it should have.
Deconstruction does not assume that once its work has been done everything will have been
included. That would be impossible. It doesn't even assume that its work will result in the
inclusion of more than was previously included; it doesn't assume that its work will make things
better. That remains to be seen in each case. In sum, deconstruction doesn't assume that there is,
even if only in principle, an end to the work of deconstruction. The point of deconstruction is to
show where something has been omitted, not because of the blindness of the author, not because
the critic is smarter or better, but because that is the way things are. There are always things I
don't know, though in a very real way that I don't know them is part of what I know.
Derrida is fascinated by this "nonknowledge" and his work circles around it:
not that I love nonknowledge for itself, on the contrary, I am even ready to think like
certain Muslims that "the ink of the learned is more sacred than the blood of the martyrs,"
but sacred, precisely, through something other than knowledge, et cum amant beatam
uitam, quod non est aliud quam de ueritate guadium, utique amant etiam ueritatem nec
amarent, nisi esset aliqua notitia eius in memoria eorum(5)
What we read or write can be sacred, but what makes it
sacred is something other than itself,
something outside the text, something that the text calls us to
remember while, at the same time,
excluding it by its implicit claim to finality and completion. Texts
strive to speak about this other-than toward which they point but that
their pointing never quite reaches; they speak toward what
is always finally omitted by the text, in spite of its or its author's
intentions.(6) The object of their
intention eludes their intention. The problem is that, in spite of itself, the text purports to have left
nothing outside itself, to have recovered what it calls us to remember; the text purports to have
moved what needs to be remembered from forgetfulness into immediacy, to have made memory
no long necessary.
Because Derrida is interested in this relation between the text and what the text aims to speak of
but cannot, some have compared his work to negative theology.(7) After some initial hesitation,
Derrida has himself made the comparison, though it would be a mistake to say that his work
constitutes a negative theology.(8) There are two moments in negative theology. One is to discover
and to say as accurately as possible the right names and descriptions of the Divine. Paradoxically,
the second is to show that these names are inadequate. For example, one must say "God is just";
it is blasphemy to say otherwise. Nevertheless, once that is established, it is also true that the
sentence is inadequate; from the point of view of a claim to have said the complete and final truth,
it is untrue. For, we only know what justice is by using our own justice as a reference point.
However, God's justice surpasses ours, so much so that it is inadequate to use the same name for
it. Thus one must also say, "God is not just" -- but readers must take care how they read what
looks like a simple denial of God's justice.
The negative theologian recognizes the absolute necessity of speaking about God. Theology is
necessary. He worries, however, that our theology may give us the impression that we are now
done with thinking about God; we may believe, at least implicitly, that our knowledge has
encompassed the infinite. So the negative theologian reminds us of God's infinity by showing us
the failure of our affirmative theology. The point is not that there is no God or that God is, in a
straightforward sense, not just, but that we must continue to speak of God, to praise him, to
wonder at his justice. Because it makes possible the continuation of the essence of first, positive,
praising moment of theology, the second moment of theology, negative theology, is not a moment
of pure denial, but as much a moment of praise as the first. For the negative theologian, true
theology comes in neither affirmative theology by itself nor in negative theology alone, but in the
"third way," the continued praise that is opened by the opposition between the two ways.
The common assumption of deconstruction and negative theology is that language necessarily
"fails" to say everything, to remember everything, but that it nevertheless says something, even
something about what it fails to recover. If we put this in terms of intention, we can say that our
intention fails to reach its object,(9) but that it nevertheless points toward something. What the text
excludes shows itself in various traces within the very texts that do the forgetting. Derrida is
interested in this "logic" of saying and not saying, of inclusion and exclusion, of presence and
absence, of speaking and silence, of memory and forgetting.
Often what is not spoken is a matter of meaning. Often, however, it is not merely a matter of
meaning. Deconstruction can be a matter of showing whom the text has omitted, overlooked, or
forgotten. There are various others whom we may forget. Sometimes we fail to remember God,
someone with whom, contrary to many expectations, Derrida continues to be concerned, though
he is not a theist:
I am addressing myself here to God, the only one I take as a witness, without yet knowing
what these sublime words mean, and this grammar, and to, and witness, and god, and take,
take God, and not only do I pray, as I have never stopped doing all my life, and pray to
him, but I take him here and take him as my witness, I give myself what he gives me, i.e.
the i.e. to take the time to take God as a witness (Circumfession 56-8)
In the last several years, at least partly because of the many misunderstandings of his work
(misunderstandings for which he admits some responsibility), Derrida has been explicit about this
focus on absence and omission as an ethical focus.(10) Like negative theology, his work is not
nihilistic or merely playful. It is not merely an exercise in a new kind of literary criticism (though it
may have implications for literary criticism). Ultimately, Derrida's work is ethical. The point of
deconstruction is to help us remember what the text calls us to remember but then forgets by its
very nature. Deconstruction calls us to the act of remembering, wonder, and praise, and in that to
a remembering relation to what we have forgotten rather than to the descriptions of what we have
forgotten. Though ideas and words and meanings are important omissions, they are not nearly so
important as are the unnameable people who are often omitted, excluded, forgotten.
Deconstruction interrupts the apparent seamlessness of texts and practices so that we have some
chance of noticing what makes those texts and practices possible, even if we can only notice "it"
in the trace or spoor that it leaves behind. It may not be possible simply to remember what we
have forgotten, but deconstruction calls us at least to remember our forgetting.
As Derrida says in Circumfession: "What we have said about writing and the trace shows that no
autos is possible without an inscription of alterity, no inside without a relation to an outside which
cannot be simply outside but must remark itself on the inside" (47-48). And, contrary to those
who see in him an advocate of anarchy or simple relativism: "The law one gives oneself retains an
irreducible relation to the law received before the law" (48).
Deconstruction is not naive about what it uncovers for us, about what it calls us to remember.
The comparison to negative theology is strong: just as Derrida's deconstruction would not repair
Heidegger's text, he does not believe that deconstruction can, by showing us our ethical and other
kinds of omissions, make it possible to exclude no one. As Derrida explains, pure hospitality,
including everyone is impossible. Actual hospitality requires decision, discrimination. That
discrimination, always a limit on hospitality, on inclusion, is indispensable. The point is not the
end of exclusion and forgetting, but our thought about them. The point is for us to face those
omissions and exclusions and, through facing them, to rethink what we are about. But Derrida is
not so naive as to believe that any rethinking will bring an end to exclusion. He is not Hegel or
Marx. Language will never capture what it aims at completely because the things there are,
whether words, material objects, persons, human relations, or God, cannot be captured fully --
and that is because to think that something could be captured fully is to think of it as static, as
without possibility, as dead in the strictest sense.
Though sentences, words, and texts are necessary, they do not have the same necessity as
wonder, praise, and reverence. In homage to that reverence, our texts provide us with the first
moment of Derrida's negative theology, affirmation; deconstruction provides us with the second,
the denial that calls us back to wonder and praise, to something other than either affirmation or
denial. Deconstruction is critical philosophy, using the word critical in its philosophic sense: it
shows the limits of the text or practice that we are examining so we can see the effects of those
limits. Sometimes meanings are affected. Sometimes someone or some group of people are.
Sometimes our relations to God are. Sometimes we may be unsure of what is effected, though we
are sure that there are effects.
As a result of deconstruction, we may rethink our aims and, as a reasonable result, continue with
something like the status quo. (The parallel with negative theology is that we may continue to say
the same things about God.) We may, instead, opt for something "new" (we may create new
theologies), but if we do we must know in advance that will we consequently omit and exclude
new groups or persons, or ideas, or . . . . Like the negative theologian, Derrida is not necessarily
arguing for a new system or approach to philosophical, literary, or ethical problems. The point is
not to replace the old theology with a new one that overcomes the mistakes of the old. Neither is
he arguing against a new system or approach. Rather, he wants us to "see" our omissions and
exclusions and "failures" so we can think through them and decide, so we can act ethically in
response to them. Derrida's work is a work of praise and reverence for others -- especially since,
with thinkers like Emmanuel Lévinas, Derrida believes that the other person, like God, always
escapes my grasp and comprehension. The other person is always absent from any merely rational
system, if for no other reason than that any embodied, material being, especially a living one,
escapes complete rationalization.
For Derrida, therefore, though deconstruction deals with texts, it is not a method for criticizing
texts, whether written, social, or otherwise. Deconstruction is an attitude, especially an ethical
attitude (using that word in the sense that Lévinas uses it, to denote fundamental relation, not
necessarily rules for living in those relations). It is an attitude by means of which one injects
theoretical and ethical humility back into the claims of texts and analyses. It is the attitude of
continuing to re-member, of continuing to praise.(11) In Aristotle's terms, deconstruction is an
attitude of continued wonder. In Socrates' terms, it is the moment of ignorance, of what
medievals later called "learned ignorance." Deconstruction is one moment in the continuation of
philosophy.
Derrida's style puts some readers off. Some of what he has said in such places as Memoires for
Paul DeMan suggests that, because of its effects in American literary criticism, Derrida has begun
to have second thoughts about the way he wrote. But his playful style is not just a result of
literary perversity. Given the premises and goals of a deconstructive reading of a text, we can
question the status of a straightforward critical essay. Such an essay, perhaps a book review, says,
"this straightforward text omits something that I can show you straightforwardly." Thus, a
straightforward response does not recognize the necessity of the omission. It stands as an
accusation of the text in question rather than as a deconstruction of it. Such accusations are
sometimes necessary. People do, after all, make mistakes. And they commit crimes and sins.
Accusation can be an appropriate response to either, but because they are comparable to the
necessary first moment of negative theology, in other words to a moment in affirmative theology,
accusations are not deconstructions (and deconstructions are not accusations). Especially in his
early work, Derrida plays with the rhetoric of response and the idea of response without
accusation, aiming to respond to the problems of the texts he examines in a manner appropriate to
his theory and, at the same time, aiming to stretch his audience.(12)
In a fragment from a long sentence that embodies what it describes, Derrida says of his writing:
I remember having gone to bed very late after a moment of anger or irony against a sentence of Proust's . . . which says: "A work in which there are theories is like an object on which one has left he price tag," and I find nothing more vulgar than this Franco-Britannic decorum . . . I admit that I write with the price on, I display, not so that the price be legible to the first-comer, for I am for an aristocracy without distinction, therefore without vulgarity, for a democracy of the compulsion to the highest price, you have to pay the price to read the price displayed (Circumfession 62-3)
Many who read Derrida's work do so without paying the price. They do not want to read deeply
and widely from the European traditions. They do not want to learn other languages. They do not
want to begin their deconstructive work with the background of careful scholarship. They are
lazy. They want to skip the first moment and deal with only the second (which is impossible).
Others are lazy because they depend on someone else's account of Derrida's work (such as this
one) or because they remain committed to the Enlightenment ideal of complete, rational
explanation without confronting the problems of that commitment. In either case, such people are
unable to read the price tag (the theory) of that work.
However, Derrida's style is not only a consequence of writing deconstructive work according to
the understanding of his theory. It is also a result of the excessive character of things themselves
and therefore texts. The excessive character of being -- that to be is to be a nexus of possibilities
rather than of determinate qualities -- means there is always play in things, experiences of things,
and descriptions, the kind of play one finds in a steering wheel, looseness and variability, give and
take more than joyfulness or silliness (though the latter are not impossible). The straightforward
text cannot but have some play in it. No text, even a deconstructive one can avoid it. Language is
like that; things themselves are like that. After Speech and Phenomena, Derrida's earlier texts
were more devoted to playing with that play, deconstructing a text by enacting the play in it in
another text. Derrida's early texts were obviously devoted to play. Less obvious to many readers,
that play was also praise. The same playful, praising element remains in all his texts, even in those
such as some of his more recent work, where it is less obvious.
Unfortunately, however one accounts for Derrida's style, the result of that style has been that
some believe his work to be only a matter of play, just a matter of doing whatever one wishes
with the text and, therefore, anything but a matter of praise and wonder. Among those who
believe this, some take it as a sign of his genius and others as a sign of his derangement. Both are
wrong. However playful it may appear at first glance, deconstruction cannot be a matter of mere
playfulness. Mere playfulness does not show us the traces in a text of what otherwise does not
appear. In fact, mere playfulness shows us only emptiness, rather than traces of the absence of
meanings, persons, and God, rather than the "failure" of our texts. Rather than calling us to
remembrance, mere playfulness suggests that there is nothing to remember. Mere playfulness is
like simple atheism rather than negative theology. Like negative theology and unlike mere
playfulness, deconstruction is also always a matter of serious purpose and careful attention to the
text or matter in question. Thus, it is not enough to object to Derrida's style as obfuscatory. It
may be opaque, intentionally so. However, that opacity is a matter of richness and fullness, a
reflection of the richness and fullness of that to which it tries to refer. (Surely neither poets nor
religious people are not generally committed to the idea that all language should be
propositionally clear and distinct. I doubt that even many empirical scientists would be so
committed.) If one is to object to Derrida, one must object to the theory of his style, a theory rich
in antecedents and implications. Dismissal will not do.
Some will doubt what I say about deconstruction. "I've never heard anything like that," they may
say, or "That's not what I learned about deconstruction." It is tempting to respond by trotting out
my "qualifications." To do so, however, is to invite comparison of my qualifications with those of
others, and some who have said ignorant things about deconstruction are nevertheless very well
qualified -- in many respects better than I. I can't win such a showdown. So, consider instead
these quotations from an interview with Jacques Derrida himself(13):
I learned a lot from my teachers. . . . This instruction was very hard and heavy, very demanding according to classical norms. I was trained in those very classical norms. And probably people who read me and think I am playing with or transgressing norms -- which I do, of course -- usually don't know what I know: that all of this has not only been made possible by but is constantly in contact with very classical, rigorous, demanding discipline in writing. . . . the fact that I am at some level true to this classical teaching is essential. . . . When I take liberties, it's always by measuring the distance from the standards I know or that I've rigorously been trained in.
Deconstruction questions the thesis, theme, the positionality of everything. . . . We have to study the models and the history of the models and then try not to subvert them for the sake of destroying them but to change the models and invent new ways of writing -- not as a formal challenge, but for ethical, political reasons.
I wouldn't approve of simply throwing texts into disorder. First, deconstructing academic professional discourse doesn't mean destroying the norms or pushing these norms to utter chaos. I'm not in favor of disorder.
I started with the tradition. If you're not trained in the tradition, then deconstruction means nothing. It's simply nothing.
I think that if what is called "deconstruction" produces neglect of the classical authors, the canonical texts, and so on, we should fight it. . . . I'm in favor of the canon, but I won't stop there. I think that students should read what are considered the great texts in our tradition. . . . Students could develop, let's say, a deconstructive practice -- but only to the extent that they "know" what they are "deconstructing": an enormous network of other questions.
I'm in favor or tradition. I'm respectful of and a lover of the tradition. There's no deconstruction without the memory of the tradition. I couldn't imagine what the university could be without reference to the tradition, but a tradition that is as rich as possible and that is open to other traditions, and so on.
Logocentrism literally, as such, is nothing else but Greek. Everywhere that the Greek culture is the dominant heritage there is logocentrism. I wouldn't draw as a conclusion, as a consequence of this, that we should simply leave it behind.
I think that people who try to represent what I'm doing or what so called "deconstruction" is doing, as, on the one hand, trying to destroy culture or, on the other hand, to reduce it to a kind of negativity, to a kind of death, are misrepresenting deconstruction. Deconstruction is essentially affirmative. It's in favor of reaffirmation of memory, but this reaffirmation of memory asks the most adventurous and the most risky questions about our tradition, about our institutions, about our way of teaching, and so on.
Consider also that in a book explaining Derrida's thought (Jacques Derrida), Derrida appends to
the bottom of each page a series of reflections in response (the appendage is Circumfession).
Derrida's reflections are autobiographical, reflections on his relation to his mother that take the
form, among others, of a response to passages from Augustine's Confessions. One cannot write
or remember in this explicit way without the benefit of a long history of autobiography,
confession, philosophy, literature, art, religion, . . . . Without a kind of obscenity, one could not
write about one's mother and her death and, at the same time, insist that texts don't matter, that
words do not signify.
The given quotations and examples from Derrida's work suggest that either deconstruction has been much misunderstood or Derrida has never explained himself well. Having read many of his works, I think the first alternative is the better explanation. In fact, though I am not a Derridean, I think that with such things in mind Derrida's work changes its character, moving from playful, irritating, but nonsensical texts to playful, irritating, demanding, and sometimes profound texts. With a long list of antecedents in Christian history and Christian philosophy, Derrida sees writing as an aid to memory:(14) its purpose is to help us remember what is always nevertheless forgotten, what only too easily slips out of our grasp, whether what we forget is what we mean, those with whom we live, or God. Derrida writes to nudge us to remember. As texts of memory, Derrida's works move from a position as texts on the margins of literary criticism and philosophical interests to texts that ask about our margins, about what is outside those, about what we have forgotten and, perhaps to our peril, ignored.
1. Though part of phenomenology's contribution to philosophy has been to demonstrate the dangers of and alternatives to speaking of ourselves as "in here," cut off from the world that is "out there," I will ignore that point for heuristic reasons.
2. It is important to note that, for Heidegger, this problem is only apparent. Historicism and relativism are mistakes consequent on the representational thinking of modernism. (See Nietzsche, vol. 2, especially section 16.)
3. Heidegger argues that this is a consequence of what it means to be at all. Thus, strictly speaking, it is not really a property of things.
4. "Ousia and Gramm: Note on a Note from Being and Time," Margins of Philosophy (Chicago: U of Chicago, 1982), 29-67.
5. "Circumfession" 141-42 (my bold), in Geoffrey Bennington and Jacques Derrida, Jacques Derrida. (Chicago: U of Chicago, 1993). The Latin is a quotation from Augustine's Confessions (X, xxiii, 33): "For they love (truth), also since they do not wish to be deceived. And, when they love the happy life, which is nothing other than joy arising from truth, they certainly love truth, also. Nor would they love it, unless some knowledge of it were in their memory."
6. One reason for some of the difficulty of Derrida's prose is that he is experimenting with form to see whether there are ways of bringing the failure of the text explicitly to the attention of the reader.
7. In, for example, Kevin Hart, The Trespass of the Sign (Cambridge: Cambridge U, 1989).
8. See, for example, the two essays in Coward and Foshay, Derrida and Negative Theology, particularly the second on Pseudo-Dionysius, "How to Avoid Speaking: Denials" (Albany: SUNY, 1992; 25-71 and 73-142).
9. More accurately, the intention does reach its object (by definition), but the object of an intention and that at which the intention purports to aim are not the same.
10. For example, see The Other Heading (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana UP, 1992) and such books as The Gift of Death (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1995), Given Time: Counterfeit Money (Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1991), and "Foi et Savoir: Les deux source de la 'religion' aux limites de la simple raison," La Religion (Paris: Seuil, 1996) 9-86.
11. Christians remember covenants via ordinances, sermons, the Christian life, etc. In other words, they remember what it means to be a Christian in their practices, which may include dogmatics, confession, and theology, but is not limited to them. One might say that Derrida looks for something like a covenantal relation in texts and philosophy. This parallel of Derrida's work to Christian theology is fascinating and fruitful, though I will not explore it here. (Those interested should begin with Hart's book.) Briefly, however, consider an example: not only is deconstruction a matter of remembrance, it is also a matter of hope and faith. In one place Derrida says: "I shall always have been eschatological if one can say so, in the extreme, I am the last of the eschatologists" (Circumfession 75). In another: "There is no morality without faith, faith in the other. There is no social experience without bearing witness, without attestation, the recognition of a dimension of trust and faith. This is not a religious point; it is the general structure of experience" (Private interview, 1 March 1996, Paris).
12. Derrida's interest in James Joyce's Ulysses, an interest that began during his days as a student at Harvard, is also behind his interest in the effects and possibilities of writing.
13. Gary A. Olsen, "Jacques Derrida on Rhetoric and Composition: A Conversation," (Inter)views: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives on Rhetoric and Literacy (Ed., Olsen and Gale), Carbondale, Illinois: Southern Illinois UP, 121-141.
14. But note the complexity of this claim created by what Derrida has to say about writing in On Grammatology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins U, 1976) and in "Plato's Pharmacy" (Chicago: U of Chicago, 1981).